The Experimental Philosophy Blog

Philosophy Meets Empirical Research

Menu
  • Home
  • About
  • Guidelines for Comments
  • Labs and Organizations
  • Resources
Menu

Priming Effects Are Fake, but Framing Effects Are Real

Posted on May 23, 2025June 6, 2025 by Joshua Knobe

A few decades ago, it was pretty common to mush together priming effects and framing effects and see them as two closely connected parts of a single Bigger Truth about the human mind. Of course, everyone understood that the effects themselves were a bit different, but one common view was that they were providing evidence for the same larger picture. That larger picture said: People’s judgments are radically unstable, easily pushed around by subtle and almost unnoticeable factors.

Things have changed so much since then. Priming research in social psychology has experienced a series of truly spectacular replication failures, while research on framing effects continues to look very solid. In light of this change, we should rethink our understanding of what framing effects show about human cognition. We shouldn’t see them as part of a larger picture that also includes priming. We need an understanding of framing that allows us to situate it within a larger picture, according to which priming effects are not real.

The priming literature seemed to be showing that people’s judgment and decision-making are highly unstable and can be easily shifted around by small manipulations of the external situation. The thought was that if you just happen to be holding a hot coffee, or sitting at a dirty desk, or in a room that includes a picture of dollar bills, your whole way of thinking about things will be shifted in some fundamental respect. For example, you will end up making deeply different moral judgments.

The key lesson of more recent research is simple: these priming effects do not occur. More generally, we cannot shift people’s moral judgments around in some radical way just by making subtle changes in their situation. Your moral judgments will not shift around completely if you are seated at a dirty desk. That is not how the human mind works.

Okay, with all of that in mind, let’s rethink framing effects. For concreteness, we can focus on a famous study from Tversky and Kahneman (1981). In this study, participants were randomly assigned to one of two conditions. Participants in the gain framing condition read the following case:

A disease is expected to kill 600 people. You can choose between two options:

  • If you choose the first option, 200 people will be saved.
  • If you choose the second option, there is one-third probability that 600 people will be saved and a two-thirds probability that 0 people will be saved.

Meanwhile, participants in the loss framing condition read:

A disease is expected to kill 600 people. You can choose between two options:

  • If you choose the first option, 400 people will die.
  • If you choose the second option, there is one-third probability that 0 people will die and a two-thirds probability that 600 people will die.

Clearly, the two descriptions are logically equivalent, but they tend to yield very different responses. Participants tend to be risk-averse in the first case, risk-seeking in the second.

During the heyday of priming research, many of us thought that this sort of effect should be understood within a larger picture of the mind that also included priming. Basically, the idea was something like this: “People’s judgments about a case can be shifted around but all sorts of little things, including everything from the decor in the room to the precise words used to describe it.” But in light of everything we know now, we need to revisit this view. Framing effects are very real, but that larger picture seems to be mistaken. We need to understand framing effects within a larger picture of the mind, according to which people’s judgments don’t just shift around randomly as a result of all sorts of little factors.

I’d be very open to different views about what the right picture is, but just as a first step in this direction, let’s consider a picture that emerges not from social psychology but rather from very traditional work in philosophy. This picture says that people often have a collection of different intuitions that are mutually inconsistent. These intuitions need not be unstable in any way. It might be that each individual intuition is completely stable; it’s just that the different intuitions contradict each other.

To illustrate, consider intuitions about free will. I might find myself having the following three intuitions: (a) All human behavior is completely explained by genes and environment, (b) If a person’s behavior is completely explained by genes and environment, that person’s behavior is not performed with free will, (c) Some human behaviors are performed with free will. These three intuitions are mutually inconsistent, so they cannot all be right. However, this does not mean that people’s free will intuitions have to be unstable in any way.

On the contrary, a single individual could easily have all three intuitions at the same time. For example, as a philosopher, I might start out a paper by explaining that each of these three claims seems intuitively to be true, that they are mutually inconsistent and hence cannot all be right, and that we therefore face an interesting philosophical problem. Alternatively, someone might simply have each of these three intuitions, but without noticing that they contradict each other. In such a case, the person would be failing to notice something important, but that would not mean that the person’s intuitions were unstable. Each of the three intuitions might be perfectly stable; it’s just that the three intuitions are not consistent.

Some philosophical problems seem to have very much the structure we see in framing effects. Consider the philosophical problem of moral luck. The problem starts with three intuitions: (a) An agent who doesn’t bring about any bad outcomes deserves relatively little blame, (b) An agent who performs the exact same behavior but who ends up bringing about a bad outcome deserves a lot of blame, (c) If the agent performs the exact same behavior in two cases and the only difference is in the outcome that ends up occurring, that difference by itself cannot be relevant to how much blame the agent deserves. I myself have all three of these intuitions. Since the intuitions are mutually inconsistent, they cannot all be right, but that does not mean that my intuitions are unstable. Each of the three intuitions is completely stable and emerges in all situations; it’s just that the three intuitions are in tension with each other.

Let’s now return to framing effects. In the days when it seemed like priming was real, I totally see why researchers would think that framing was a lot like priming. But in light of subsequent studies, maybe we should see it in a completely different way. Framing does not involve people’s judgments being unstable; it instead involves people having different intuitions that are mutually inconsistent.

Take the example described above. Looking at that example, I have the following three intuitions: (a) The correct answer in the first case is to take the non-risky option, (b) The correct answer in the second case is to take the risky option, and (c) It cannot possibly be the case that the correct answer in the first case is different from the correct answer in the second case. These three intuitions are mutually inconsistent, so they cannot all be right. However, each individual intuition can be perfectly stable. In fact, thinking about the problem right now, I find myself having all three intuitions at the same time.

Turning the traditional view about framing effects upside down, one might even see framing effects as an extreme case of stability. Just as we continue to experience a visual illusion even when we know that it is illusory, we continue to have the inconsistent intuitions that together constitute a framing effect even when we know that they cannot all be right.

[I discuss this issue in this paper, but please feel free to respond to this blog post even if you haven’t looked at the full paper.]

Tags: FramingPrimingReplication
Category: Philosophy of MindUncategorized

Post navigation

← Hot Off The Press: “The Cambridge Handbook of Experimental Jurisprudence”
Experimenting With Guesses →

9 thoughts on “Priming Effects Are Fake, but Framing Effects Are Real”

  1. Koen Smets says:
    May 23, 2025 at 18:13

    Cool insight!
    I don’t think I have ever considered priming and framing closely related—one is assumed to occur unconsciously, while the other is clearly a conscious process—but it’s easy to see them as similar if you assume a common cause, namely unstable judgments.
    The comparison with bistable optical illusions works well for me—the parallel is not so much focus on different aspect, but *interpreting* the same aspects differently. It’s not too much of a stretch to restate the duckrabbit as “the same pixels framed as either a set of ears, or as a bill”, and the subsequent pattern recognition as ‘intuition’.
    In your example, the third intuition seems like a meta-intuition, and I think that adds depth and support to the hypothesis of inconsistent intuitions.
    I think it might be most interesting to explore this inconsistent intuitions perspective to framing instances beyond K&T’s classic loss/gain framing, eg in social relationships or motivations for certain actions. (You may have done that in the paper you refer to—I’ve not had a chance to look at it yet.)

    Reply
  2. Joshua Knobe says:
    May 23, 2025 at 18:52

    Hi Koen,

    Thanks! Could you say a little bit more about what you have in mind regarding framing in social relationships or motivations for action? This sounds really intriguing, but I fear that maybe I’m not already familiar with the studies you are thinking thinking of here.

    Reply
  3. Louis Chartrand says:
    May 23, 2025 at 21:09

    I feel that “priming effects are fake” needs some qualification. There are real priming effects in some domains, like detection of simple stimuli. Priming with apple makes it easier to detect “orange”. Conversely, priming can interfere with a task and make it slower and less accurate, if it mobilizes the same resources (take the word color tasks). Maybe you meant “in social psychology”?

    Reply
  4. Joshua Knobe says:
    May 23, 2025 at 21:12

    Good point! I modified the second paragraph so that it now says “Priming research in social psychology…”

    Reply
  5. Koen Smets says:
    May 23, 2025 at 21:14

    Hello Joshua,
    I wasn’t thinking of any particular papers or research, but about instances of framing more generally—for example a conflict in a romantic relationship can be framed as an issue to be resolved collaboratively (maybe an unorthodox case of adversarial collaboration, where both partners seem the same truth but hope it’ll be *theirs* 😎), or as an issue of winning or losing; a parent-child conflict over homework can be framed as the child seeking independence or as the child being defiant and disobedient. A person or a company making a charitable donation can be genuinely motivated by a desire to contribute to a better world, or by virtue signalling or self-serving aims. Climate activism can be framed as securing survival (curb carbon emissions) or as politically motivated (reverse growth). In such cases (and many more), we also have intuitions, which may well be equally incompatible as those in logically simpler loss/gain framing.
    I hope this makes sense!

    Reply
  6. Joshua Knobe says:
    May 23, 2025 at 22:07

    Thanks Koen! This is all super helpful.

    Reply
    1. Koen Smets says:
      May 24, 2025 at 04:19

      Great!
      In the meantime I thought of another potentially interesting example of framing—Arnold Kling’s Three Languages of Politics. Just about any political issue can be framed as civilization vs barbarism (conservative framing), oppressor vs oppressed (liberal framing), or freedom vs coercion (libertarian framing). For most people these are not rigidly held, and while one might be the default, many might harbour two or all three types of intuitions. That is arguably not so different from a default relatively risk-seeking or risk-averse disposition in the K&T Asian Disease case, which can be overridden by the framing.

      Reply
  7. Joshua Knobe says:
    May 24, 2025 at 23:49

    Hi Koen,

    Thanks once again. This idea brings up all sorts of fascinating questions, but for the purposes of the more narrow point I was making in my post, the big question is simply whether (a) this framing effect involves something like temporarily changing one’s mode of thought or whether (b) it is possible to have the various different intuition all at the same time.

    For example, suppose there is a single policy that seems good when framed in terms of in terms of civilization vs barbarism but seems bad when framed in terms of oppressor vs oppressed. The key question would be whether this is something like what priming effects were supposed to be, where you can temporarily get into a mode of thinking in terms of oppressor vs oppressed and then see everything within that lens and as long as you are thinking in that way you can’t see the other perspectives. Alternatively, it could be something more like what philosophical paradox is were supposed to be, where you can feel in a single moment the tension between these different perspectives and see how the very same policy appears to be good in one way but bad in another.

    Reply
  8. Koen Smets says:
    May 27, 2025 at 16:44

    That is indeed exactly the question I have as well. I operationalize it as having de facto contradicting intuitions, in the sense that, *for certain particular policies*, one’s intuition with the oppressor/oppressed perspective might support it, but one’s intuition with the civilization/barbarians perspective would oppose it (while other policy choice might intuitively be favoured or objected to from either perspective). This is much like we may (and do) end up with paradoxical or contradictory preferences: eg a dream job, but in an industry with which one has moral qualms; a top quality electric car, but made by a company led by a hated CEO; being strongly vegan leaning but unable to resist fried bacon etc.
    It’s not quite the same, but exhibits strong similarities I think.

    Reply

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *


Search

Categories

Tags

Agency Artificial Intelligence Basic Needs Beauty Behavior Beliefs Bias Bioethics Blame Causation Cognitive Science Consciousness Corpus Analysis Cross-Cultural Research Desires Determinism Distributive Justice Emotions Essentialism Expertise Expressives Folk Morality Framing Free Will Gender Intention Intuition Jurisprudence Knowledge Large Language Models Luck Norms Objectivism Pejoratives Problem of Evil Psycholinguistics Reasoning Reflective Equilibrium Replication Responsibility Self Side-Effect Effect Slurs Valence Virtue

Recent Posts

  • Conference: “Basel-Oxford-NUS BioXPhi Summit”
  • Experimenting With Guesses
  • Priming Effects Are Fake, but Framing Effects Are Real
  • Hot Off The Press: “The Cambridge Handbook of Experimental Jurisprudence”
  • Do People Think That Free Will Is Incompatible with Determinism?

Recent Comments

  1. Koen Smets on Priming Effects Are Fake, but Framing Effects Are RealMay 27, 2025

    That is indeed exactly the question I have as well. I operationalize it as having de facto contradicting intuitions, in…

  2. Joshua Knobe on Priming Effects Are Fake, but Framing Effects Are RealMay 24, 2025

    Hi Koen, Thanks once again. This idea brings up all sorts of fascinating questions, but for the purposes of the…

  3. Koen Smets on Priming Effects Are Fake, but Framing Effects Are RealMay 24, 2025

    Great! In the meantime I thought of another potentially interesting example of framing—Arnold Kling’s Three Languages of Politics. Just about…

  4. Joshua Knobe on Priming Effects Are Fake, but Framing Effects Are RealMay 23, 2025

    Thanks Koen! This is all super helpful.

  5. Koen Smets on Priming Effects Are Fake, but Framing Effects Are RealMay 23, 2025

    Hello Joshua, I wasn’t thinking of any particular papers or research, but about instances of framing more generally—for example a…

Archives

  • June 2025
  • May 2025
  • April 2025
  • March 2025
  • February 2025
  • January 2025
  • December 2024
  • November 2024
  • October 2024
  • September 2024
  • August 2024
  • July 2024
  • June 2024
  • May 2024
  • April 2024
  • March 2024

Meta

  • Log in
  • Entries feed
  • Comments feed
  • WordPress.org

Imprint • Disclaimer • Privacy Statement • Cookie Policy

© 2024 The Experimental Philosophy Blog
Manage Consent
To provide the best experiences, we use technologies like cookies to store and/or access device information. Consenting to these technologies will allow us to process data such as browsing behavior or unique IDs on this site. Not consenting or withdrawing consent, may adversely affect certain features and functions.
Functional Always active
The technical storage or access is strictly necessary for the legitimate purpose of enabling the use of a specific service explicitly requested by the subscriber or user, or for the sole purpose of carrying out the transmission of a communication over an electronic communications network.
Preferences
The technical storage or access is necessary for the legitimate purpose of storing preferences that are not requested by the subscriber or user.
Statistics
The technical storage or access that is used exclusively for statistical purposes. The technical storage or access that is used exclusively for anonymous statistical purposes. Without a subpoena, voluntary compliance on the part of your Internet Service Provider, or additional records from a third party, information stored or retrieved for this purpose alone cannot usually be used to identify you.
Marketing
The technical storage or access is required to create user profiles to send advertising, or to track the user on a website or across several websites for similar marketing purposes.
Manage options Manage services Manage {vendor_count} vendors Read more about these purposes
View Preferences
{title} {title} {title}