The Experimental Philosophy Blog

Philosophy Meets Empirical Research

Menu
  • Home
  • About
  • Guidelines for Comments
  • Labs and Organizations
  • Resources
Menu

The Folk Concept of Art

Posted on March 5, 2025March 5, 2025 by Elzė Sigutė Mikalonytė

What makes an object art? Many different answers may come to mind. Works of art are typically beautiful or possess different kinds of aesthetic value. We may seek them out when we want to satisfy our need for aesthetic experiences. Works of art are usually the result of creative actions guided by artistic intentions. Some of us would emphasize historical and institutional conventions in determining what is worthy of being called art. At other times, we engage with art to fulfill a need for emotional experiences, choosing objects that are emotionally expressive. Many would argue that a work of art must be intellectually challenging or convey complex meanings, or that it must demonstrate a high degree of skill on behalf of its creator. Others would emphasize certain formal qualities, such as complexity. The list of possible factors that make an object art is far from exhaustive.

Philosophers aiming to find the best definition of art defend one of two approaches. The first sees the concept of art as definable in terms of individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions. These definitions often emphasize one condition that must be met for an object to be considered art – for instance, being intentionally created, being capable of providing people with aesthetic experiences, or being institutionally recognised by art critics or art historians. Philosophers who support this view offer essentialist theories of art.

The second approach denies that it is possible to define art through individually necessary conditions. It draws on the Wittgensteinian idea of open concepts, where members of a category are instead united by family resemblances. The list of properties that make an object art is seen either as a long disjunction, or a cluster where the list of properties may change over time. This second approach can be called non-essentialist theories of art.

Which of these approaches is more compatible with the folk concept of art? In our new paper, we present evidence that the folk concept of art resembles more the second type of art theories, that is, the folk concept of art is an open rather than closed concept.

Our Studies

Across two studies, we explored two questions. First, as already mentioned, we were interested in whether the folk concept of art is an open or a closed concept. We also examined the role of three factors – intentional creation, aesthetic value, and institutional recognition – in art categorisation judgments. These three factors are not only among the most frequently mentioned properties in the philosophical literature, but also have some support from psychological research.

In Study 1, which was a 2 × 2 × 2 between-subjects design study, we manipulated all three of the above-mentioned features: whether an object was created intentionally, whether it is beautiful, and whether it received institutional recognition. Each participant was assigned to one of eight conditions composed of the following elements (+ for presence, – for absence of each feature):

Intention

  • [+] A person decides to create a painting. She takes an empty canvas and applies paint onto it.
  • [–] A person accidentally brushes against some jars of paint that spill onto an empty canvas.

Beauty

  • [+] The resulting object looks beautiful, featuring an elegant interplay of different lines of paint. It captures the viewers’ attention and evokes awe and wonder.
  • [−] The resulting object looks ordinary and uninteresting. It leaves the viewers bored and unimpressed.

Recognition

  • [+] Soon this object gets recognized by art critics, finds its way into a museum and some years later it appears in art history books.
  • [−] This object never gets exhibited in art galleries or museums, and it never receives any attention from art critics.

We asked the participants the extent to which they agreed (on a Likert scale from 1 (completely disagree) to 7 (completely agree)) with the following statements:

  • “The object is art.” [Art]
  • “The object was made by an artist.” [Artist]
  • “The person wanted to make a painting.” [Desire]
  • “The person believed they were making a painting.” [Belief]
  • “The person intentionally made a painting.” [Intent]

We found that the presence of each of the three factors increased the likelihood that the painting would be called art. Beauty alone was considered a sufficient condition – that is, beautiful objects were considered art even if they were created accidentally and not institutionally recognised. Intentional creation alone was also considered sufficient by itself. Institutional recognition, however, was not.

People were more likely to consider the creator an artist if the painting was made intentionally rather than unintentionally; however, beauty or recognition did not have an influence on these judgments. We also found that all three mental states (intention, desire, and belief) correlated with both “art” and “artist” ratings.

In Study 2, we used an almost identical scenario, except that in this case, we explored people’s intuitions in the context of music. Vignettes were composed of the following elements:

Intention

  • [+] A person decides to compose a piece of music. She opens a blank stave sheet on a music notation software, writes notes on it, and carefully chooses instrumentation.
  • [−] A person uses a new music notation software for the first time. She opens a blank stave sheet, writes random notes on it, and chooses random instrumentation.

Beauty

  • [+] The result sounds beautiful, featuring an elegant interplay of parts. It captures the listeners’ attention and evokes awe and wonder.
  • [−] The result sounds ordinary and uninteresting. It leaves the listeners bored and unimpressed.

Recognition

  • [+] Soon the piece gets recognized by music critics, is performed in concert halls and some years later it appears in music history books.
  • [−] The piece never gets played in concert halls, and it never receives any attention from music critics.

The results of Study 2 were largely the same as before, except that in this study, institutional recognition by itself (in the absence of beauty or intention) was also considered sufficient for an object to be art. The presence of each of the three factors increased the likelihood that the creator would be considered an artist. Both intentional creation or beauty were sufficient for the creator to be called an artist.

Our results show that none of the three factors are considered by the folk to be individually necessary for an object to be art. However, each of them (with the exception of institutional recognition in the visual domain) was considered sufficient. Our results therefore suggest that the folk concept of art is a non-essentialist concept. We examined only three features in our studies – these results should be confirmed with a larger number of potential properties.

Surprisingly, our results go against a widely held position in aesthetics: the idea that artworks, just like other artifacts, must be intentionally created. We found that in some cases, people are willing to call objects art even if they came into being without intention. Moreover, they are sometimes willing to consider an object art even if they do not consider its creator an artist.

To see full results and discussion, you can access our paper here: https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s11229-024-04812-8

Literature

Mikalonytė, Elzė Sigutė, and Markus Kneer (2024): “The Folk Concept of Art,” Synthese 205, 2. (Link)

Tags: ArtEssentialismFamily Resemblance
Category: Aesthetics

Post navigation

← Talk: “Derogatory Speech – Conversations, Hearers, and Listeners” (Claire Horisk)
Call: “Cognitive Tools in Action” →

1 thought on “The Folk Concept of Art”

  1. Nova Praxis says:
    July 11, 2025 at 09:38

    This article highlights an important point: everyday people don’t rely on rigid definitions to determine what qualifies as art. They’re often willing to recognize something as “art” even if it lacks traditional elements like clear artistic intent or institutional endorsement. This openness may help explain the growing public acceptance – or at least tolerance – of AI-generated artworks, despite their lack of human authorship or personal expression.

    At the same time, a compelling piece by transdisciplinary philosopher Prof. Nayef Al-Rodhan, titled “How do we set the moral compass on AI-generated art?”, sheds light on a critical issue: while cultural perceptions may evolve quickly, ethical and legal frameworks often lag behind. Even if the public embraces AI-generated works as valid forms of art, questions around authorship, ownership, and moral accountability remain unresolved for creators and institutions.

    This tension reveals a deeper challenge: as technology reshapes the boundaries of art, our ethical frameworks and definitions must evolve – not only to accommodate new tools, but also to reflect shifting public intuitions.
    Prof. Al-Rodhan’s article is well worth reading: https://capx.co/how-do-we-set-the-moral-compass-on-ai-generated-art

    Reply

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *


Search

Categories

Tags

Agency Artificial Intelligence Basic Needs Beauty Behavior Beliefs Bias Bioethics Blame Causation Cognitive Science Consciousness Corpus Analysis Cross-Cultural Research Determinism Distributive Justice Emotions Essentialism Expertise Expressives Folk Morality Framing Free Will Gender Intention Intuition Jurisprudence Knowledge Large Language Models Luck Norms Objectivism Pejoratives Problem of Evil Psycholinguistics Reasoning Reflective Equilibrium Replication Responsibility Self Side-Effect Effect Slurs Truth Valence Virtue

Recent Posts

  • Hot Off The Press: “Empirical Studies on Questions of Need-Based Distributive Justice”
  • Call: “Valence Asymmetries”
  • Talk: “Intentionality and Discrimination”
  • Call: “Folk Epistemology”
  • Call: “Philosophers on Philosophy”

Recent Comments

  1. Nova Praxis on The Folk Concept of ArtJuly 11, 2025

    This article highlights an important point: everyday people don’t rely on rigid definitions to determine what qualifies as art. They’re…

  2. Koen Smets on Priming Effects Are Fake, but Framing Effects Are RealMay 27, 2025

    That is indeed exactly the question I have as well. I operationalize it as having de facto contradicting intuitions, in…

  3. Joshua Knobe on Priming Effects Are Fake, but Framing Effects Are RealMay 24, 2025

    Hi Koen, Thanks once again. This idea brings up all sorts of fascinating questions, but for the purposes of the…

  4. Koen Smets on Priming Effects Are Fake, but Framing Effects Are RealMay 24, 2025

    Great! In the meantime I thought of another potentially interesting example of framing—Arnold Kling’s Three Languages of Politics. Just about…

  5. Joshua Knobe on Priming Effects Are Fake, but Framing Effects Are RealMay 23, 2025

    Thanks Koen! This is all super helpful.

Archives

  • October 2025
  • September 2025
  • August 2025
  • July 2025
  • June 2025
  • May 2025
  • April 2025
  • March 2025
  • February 2025
  • January 2025
  • December 2024
  • November 2024
  • October 2024
  • September 2024
  • August 2024
  • July 2024
  • June 2024
  • May 2024
  • April 2024
  • March 2024

Meta

  • Log in
  • Entries feed
  • Comments feed
  • WordPress.org

Imprint • Disclaimer • Privacy Statement • Cookie Policy

© 2024 The Experimental Philosophy Blog
Manage Consent
To provide the best experiences, we use technologies like cookies to store and/or access device information. Consenting to these technologies will allow us to process data such as browsing behavior or unique IDs on this site. Not consenting or withdrawing consent, may adversely affect certain features and functions.
Functional Always active
The technical storage or access is strictly necessary for the legitimate purpose of enabling the use of a specific service explicitly requested by the subscriber or user, or for the sole purpose of carrying out the transmission of a communication over an electronic communications network.
Preferences
The technical storage or access is necessary for the legitimate purpose of storing preferences that are not requested by the subscriber or user.
Statistics
The technical storage or access that is used exclusively for statistical purposes. The technical storage or access that is used exclusively for anonymous statistical purposes. Without a subpoena, voluntary compliance on the part of your Internet Service Provider, or additional records from a third party, information stored or retrieved for this purpose alone cannot usually be used to identify you.
Marketing
The technical storage or access is required to create user profiles to send advertising, or to track the user on a website or across several websites for similar marketing purposes.
  • Manage options
  • Manage services
  • Manage {vendor_count} vendors
  • Read more about these purposes
View Preferences
  • {title}
  • {title}
  • {title}